Skepticism
Skepticism
(or Scepticism in the UK spelling) is a Hellenistic school of
philosophy. At its simplest, Skepticism holds that one should refrain
from making truth claims, and avoid the postulation of final
truths. This is not necessarily quite the same as claiming that truth is impossible
(which would itself be a truth claim), but is often also used to cover the
position that there is no such thing as certainty in human knowledge
(sometimes referred to as Academic Skepticism). See the section on the doctrine
of Skepticism for more details.
Possibly
the earliest Skeptic, Gorgias claimed that nothing exists; or, if
something does exist, then it cannot be known; or if something does
exist and can be known, it cannot be communicated. Gorgias, however, is
known primarily as a Sophist rather than as a philosophical skeptic.
Socrates
claimed that he knew one and only one thing: that he knew nothing.
Thus, rather than making assertions or opinions, he set about
questioning people who claimed to have knowledge, ostensibly for the
purpose of learning from them. Although he never claimed that knowledge
is impossible, he never claimed to have discovered any piece of
knowledge whatsoever, even at his death.
The first
Skeptic proper, however, was Pyrrho of Elis (although he was perhaps not
actually a "skeptic" in the later sense of the word), and the
Skeptic movement which subsequently grew up was largely based around his early
ideas. Pyrrho traveled and studied as far as India, but he became overwhelmed
by his inability to determine rationally which of the various competing
schools of thought of the time was correct. Upon admitting this to
himself, he finally achieved the inner peace (or "ataraxia")
that he had been seeking (and which became the ultimate goal of the
early Skeptikoi), and he propounded the adoption of what he called "practical
skepticism". Pyrrho himself wrote nothing, and even the satiric
writings of his pupil Timon of Phlius are mostly lost. Today, his ideas
are known mainly through the book "Outlines of Pyrrhonism"
by the Greek physician Sextus Empiricus in the early 3rd Century A.D.
Later
thinkers took up and extended Pyrrho's approach, accusing the Stoics of dogmatism,
and arguing that the logical mode of argument was untenable, as
it relied on propositions which could not be said to be either true or false
without relying on further propositions. They did not believe that truth
was necessarily unobtainable, but rather an idea which did not yet
exist in a pure form, or had not yet been discovered. Thus, they
viewed dogmatism as a disease of the mind and vowed to continue their
inquiry.
Around 266
B.C., Arcesilaus (c. 316 - 241 B.C.) became head of Plato's Academy
in Athens, and he strongly changed the Academy's emphasis from Platonism to
Skepticism, and it remained the center of "Academic Skepticism"
for the next two centuries. Carneades (c. 214 - 129 B.C.), who became
the fourth Academy scholarch in succession after Arcesilaus in 155 B.C., was
one of the best known of the Academic Skeptics, and he famously claimed
that "Nothing can be known, not even this". He was followed as head
of the Academy by Clitomachus (187 - 109 B.C.) in 129 B.C., and by Philo
of Larissa (c. 159 - 84 B.C.) who became the last undisputed head of
the Academy in 110 B.C. until the Roman occupation in 84 B.C.
During the
1st Century B.C., Aenesidemus rejected many of the theories of the
Academy and founded a separate Pyrrhonian Skepticism school, which revived
the principle of epoche" (or "suspended judgment")
originally proposed by Pyrrho and Timon, as a solution to what he considered to
be the insoluble problems of Epistemology.
Later
followers of Pyrrho and Carneades developed more theoretical perspectives,
and Sextus Empiricus (c. 200 A.D.) in particular incorporated aspects of
Empiricism (the idea that the origin of all knowledge is sense
experience) into the basis for asserting knowledge. Sextus and his
followers considered both the claims to know and not to know to
be equally dogmatic, and claimed neither. Instead, despite the
apparent conflict with the goal of ataraxia, they claimed to continue
searching for something that might be knowable.
After
centuries of religious dogmatism throughout the Middle Ages, Skepticism
again resurfaced during the Age of Reason and the Enlightenment
of the 17th and 18th Century. Michel de Montaigne (1533 - 1592) in
France and Francis Bacon in England both took as their starting point the skeptical
viewpoint that they knew nothing for certain, as did Blaise Pascal
and René Descartes, although these early pioneers were careful not to
jettison their Christian beliefs.
Descartes
established a methodological skepticism (also known as Cartesian
Skepticism) in which he rejected any idea that can be doubted,
and then attempted to re-establish it in order to acquire a firm foundation for
genuine knowledge. His famous formulation "Cogito, ergo sum"
is sometimes stated as "Dubito, ergo cogito, ergo sum"
("I doubt, therefore I think, therefore I am").
No comments:
Post a Comment